FILED: September 29, 2005
IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF OREGON
STATE OF OREGON,
Respondent on Review,
v.
CHARLES ROBERT CIANCANELLI,
Petitioner on Review.
(CC 98CR2685FE; CA A108122; SC S49707)
On review from the Court of Appeals.*
Argued and submitted November 3, 2003.
Robin A. Jones, Senior Deputy Public Defender, Salem, argued the cause and filed the briefs for petitioner on review. With her on the briefs were Peter A. Ozanne, Executive Director, and Peter Gartlan, Chief Defender, Oregon Public Defense Services.
Charles Robert Ciancanelli, petitioner on review, filed the briefs for himself.
Robert M. Atkinson, Assistant Attorney General, Salem, argued the cause and filed the briefs for respondent on review. With him on the briefs were Hardy Myers, Attorney General, and Mary H. Williams, Solicitor General.
Charles F. Hinkle, Portland, filed the brief for amicus curiae ACLU Foundation of Oregon, Inc. and for amici curiae Oregonian Publishing Company and other media entities. With him on the brief for Oregonian Publishing Company and other media entities was Stoel Rives LLP.
Chin See Ming, of Perkins Coie LLP, Portland, filed the brief for amici curiae ACLU Foundation of Oregon, Inc. and White Bird. With him on the brief were Julia E. Markley and Les Swanson.
Bradley J. Woodworth and Lake James H. Perriguey, of Bradley J. Woodworth & Associates, PC, Portland, filed the briefs for amicus curiae Portland Area Privacy Alliance.
Before Carson, Chief Justice, and Gillette, Durham, Riggs, De Muniz, and Balmer, Justices.**
GILLETTE, J.
The decision of the Court of Appeals is affirmed in part and reversed in part. The case is remanded to the circuit court.
De Muniz, J., dissented and filed an opinion.
*Appeal from Douglas County Circuit Court, Joan S. Seitz, Judge. 181 Or App 1, 45 P3d 451 (2002).
**Kistler, J., did not participate in the consideration or decision of this case.
GILLETTE, J.
In this criminal proceeding, we are asked to decide whether ORS 167.062, which makes it a crime to, among other things, "direct, manage, finance or present" a "live public show" in which the participants engage in "sexual conduct" violates the free expression rights guaranteed by Article I, section 8, of the Oregon Constitution. (1) Drawing on the "Robertson framework," (2) which this court uses to address free expression issues that arise under Article I, section 8, defendant argues that the statute is unconstitutional because it is directed, by its terms, at a form of expression and does not fall within a well-established "historical exception" to the constitutional prohibition on enactment of such laws.
The state disagrees that ORS 167.062 is directed at expression and, for that reason, argues that the statute is constitutionally sound under State v. Robertson, 293 Or 402, 649 P2d 569 (1983). However, the state also contends, on a more fundamental level, that the analytical underpinnings of the Robertson framework are unsound. It follows, the state asserts, that this court should re-examine that framework and disavow it in favor of a form of "balancing" test that (in the view of the state) more correctly captures the true meaning and scope of Article I, section 8.
For reasons that we set out post, we disagree with the state's assertion that the statute is not, by its terms, aimed at expression. We therefore conclude that this case is one to which the Robertson framework applies. Respecting that methodology, we accept the state's request that we consider its criticisms of Robertson. Having done so, we conclude that the state has failed to show that Robertson is incorrect. We therefore adhere to it. Furthermore, we reject categorically the state's proffered alternative, balancing test.
I. FACTS AND PROCEDURAL BACKGROUND
The following facts are supported by the record. Defendant operated an "adult-oriented" business, Angels, in Roseburg. Angels offered a menu of "shows," to be performed for individual customers or small groups upon payment of a fee. The shows were presented in a small room on the premises.
Undercover policemen visited Angels on two occasions. During the first visit, the officers requested and paid for a "toy show." A female employee of Angels led them into a room and proceeded to "perform" for them by, among other things, removing her clothing and inserting a dildo and her finger into her vagina. During the second visit, the officers paid for a "two girl show." During that show, two women performed a striptease, rubbed their breasts against the officers chests, and engaged in oral sex with one another.
After the second visit, the officers arrested defendant and the performers. Defendant later was charged by indictment with two counts of promoting a live sex show, ORS 167.062, one count of promoting prostitution, ORS 167.012, two counts of compelling prostitution, ORS 167.017, and two counts of using a child in a display of sexual conduct, ORS 163.670 (the latter two counts are based on the fact that one of defendant's performers was under 18 years of age). Before trial, defendant demurred to the indictment, arguing, among other things, that ORS 167.062, on its face, and ORS 167.012, as applied to the conduct at issue, violate the free expression guarantee of Article I, section 8, of the Oregon Constitution and the free speech guarantee in the First Amendment to the United States Constitution. The trial court overruled the demurrers, and the case proceeded to trial. Defendant was convicted of all charges.
On his direct appeal to the Court of Appeals, defendant assigned error, inter alia, to the trial court's ruling on his demurrer, again arguing that ORS 167.062 is facially unconstitutional and that ORS 167.012 is unconstitutional as applied to his case. A majority of the Court of Appeals rejected both arguments. The Court of Appeals majority began by accepting, for the sake of argument, the proposition that a live sex show has content that qualifies as "expression" under Article I, section 8. State v. Ciancanelli, 181 Or App 1, 7, 45 P3d 451 (2002). Utilizing the analytical framework for challenges under Article I, section 8, that this court set out in Robertson, the Court of Appeals majority nonetheless concluded that ORS 167.062 falls within a "well-established" historical exception to the general prohibition in Article I, section 8, against laws that, by their terms, restrain expression. Id. at 19. The majority found support for that conclusion in a line of statutes and cases dating back to the seventeenth century which, taken as a whole, suggest that public nudity and sexual conduct long have been a subject of governmental regulation and punishment in the United States. The majority also relied on the fact that, in the early days of Oregon, it was a crime to expose one's private parts or otherwise to exhibit oneself in a way that is "offensive to decency, or is adapted to excite vicious or lewd thoughts or acts." Id. at 12 (quoting General Laws of Oregon, ch 48, § 632, p 559 (Deady 1845-1864)).
In a similar vein, the Court of Appeals majority held that the conduct that is the subject of ORS 167.012 (promoting prostitution) also falls wholly within a longstanding historical exception to Article I, section 8. And, because it does fall within such an exception, the majority concluded that, even if defendant were correct in suggesting that some of the conduct prohibited by ORS 167.012 is or can be "expression," that fact would not raise a constitutional issue. Ciancanelli, 181 Or App at 28-31.
II. METHODOLOGY
On review, defendant argues that the Court of Appeals majority's analysis is contrary to this court's holding in State v. Henry, 302 Or 510, 520-23, 732 P2d 9 (1987), that such early restrictions on sexually explicit or obscene expressions between adults as may have existed were not "well established" at the time that early freedoms of expression were adopted or at the time of the adoption of Article I, section 8. Defendant also argues that the Court of Appeals relied almost entirely on cases and statutes pertaining to "lewd" conduct before a nonconsenting public, but pointed to no real evidence of the historical treatment of private, sexually explicit performances staged for consenting adults. (3)
For its part, the state does not dwell on whether criminal prosecution for promoting a live sex show or prostitution falls within a "historical exception" for purposes of the Robertson framework. Instead, it focuses its argument on two points: (1) that the statutes at issue are directed at conduct, not expression; and (2) that, in any event, the entire Robertson framework should be abandoned because it is "inconsistent with what language and history teach about the intentions of the [Oregon] constitution's authors." Respecting the latter point, the state notes that, in recent years, this court has utilized a consistent methodology to construe provisions of the Oregon Constitution and has stated repeatedly that its ultimate purpose is to ascertain the intent of the provision's framers and of the people who voted to adopt it. See, e.g., Stranahan v. Fred Meyer, Inc., 331 Or 38, 54, 11 P3d 228 (2000) (describing methodology and purpose). The state further asserts that this court did not construe Article I, section 8, in Robertson by means of that methodology. The state suggests that, under those circumstances, Robertson should be set aside and Article I, section 8, should be interpreted by means of this court's present methodological paradigm.
In Stranahan, this court summarized the circumstances under which, in spite of the salutary doctrine of stare decisis, it will reconsider rules arising out of earlier decisions respecting the Oregon Constitution:
"[W]e remain willing to reconsider a previous ruling under the Oregon Constitution whenever a party presents to us a principled argument suggesting that, in an earlier decision, this court wrongly considered or wrongly decided the issue in question. We will give particular attention to arguments that either present new information as to the meaning of the constitutional provision at issue or that demonstrate some failure on the part of this court at the time of the earlier decisions to follow its usual paradigm for considering and construing the meaning of the provision in question."
Stranahan, 331 Or at 54. As noted, the state has argued that, in Robertson, this court failed to follow its "usual paradigm" for construing a provision of the Oregon Constitution.
The "usual paradigm" referred to in Stranahan for analyzing an original provision of the Oregon Constitution (such as Article I, section 8) is the one that this court first specifically identified and described in Priest v. Pearce, 314 Or 411, 840 P2d 65 (1992). There, we indicated that our search for the intent of those who drafted and adopted an original constitutional provision would address three separate topics: the wording of the constitutional provision, the case law surrounding it, and the historical circumstances leading to its adoption. Id. at 415-16. The purpose of our inquiry under the Priest methodology is "to understand the wording [of the constitutional provision] in the light of the way that the wording would have been understood and used by those who created the provision * * * and to apply faithfully the principles embodied in the Oregon Constitution to modern circumstances as those circumstances arise." Smothers v. Gresham Transfer, Inc., 332 Or 83, 90-91, 23 P3d 333 (2001) (internal quotations and citations omitted).
In the decade since the court decided Priest, this court consistently has applied that methodology to construe a number of provisions of the Oregon Constitution. See, e.g., Neher v. Chartier, 319 Or 417, 422-28, 879 P2d 156 (1994) (utilizing methodology to construe Article I, section 10, of the Oregon Constitution); Greist v. Phillips, 322 Or 281, 296-97, 906 P2d 789 (1995)(same respecting Article VII (Amended), section 3, of the Oregon Constitution); Vannatta v. Keisling, 324 Or 514, 529-36, 931 P2d 770 (1997) (same respecting Article II, section 8, of the Oregon Constitution); State v. Vasquez, 336 Or 598, 604-13, 88 P3d 271 (2004) (same respecting Article I, section 10, and Article VII (Amended), section 5, of the Oregon Constitution).
Relying on this court's expressed willingness in Stranahan to reconsider allegedly erroneous constitutional decisions, the state proffers an alternative rule to Robertson, supported by an extensive exposition of the wording of, the history respecting, and the case law decided under Article I, section 8. Defendant weighs in with an equally able brief supporting the Robertson framework, and various amici offer further help. Before addressing those arguments, however, we wish to add a note respecting requests that this court reconsider constitutional doctrine.
A decent respect for the principle of stare decisis dictates that this court should assume that its fully considered prior cases are correctly decided. Put another way, the principle of stare decisis means that the party seeking to change a precedent must assume responsibility for affirmatively persuading us that we should abandon that precedent.
Various considerations may add to that responsibility. The most common such consideration is time. Many decisions of this court serve as precedent in later decisions. Thus, disavowing one case may undermine the precedential significance of several others.
The contrast between Stranahan and this case illustrates the foregoing principle. In Stranahan, the allegedly erroneous decision had been rendered less than 10 years earlier, and few intervening precedents had relied on the earlier case, Lloyd Corporation v. Whiffen, 315 Or 500, 849 P2d 446 (1993). The Stranahan majority simply acted at the earliest possible moment to correct what it perceived to be an analytical mistake made in the immediately preceding case, Lloyd Corporation. The present case, by contrast, involves a challenge not only to Robertson, but also to the many cases that this court has decided since 1983 that have utilized its methodology.
It follows from the foregoing that the state, in order to prevail in this case, must persuade us, first, that the constitutional rule that it attacks was not formulated either by means of the appropriate paradigm or by some suitable substitute. If the state accomplishes that task, then it still has before it the more difficult task of persuading this court that application of the appropriate paradigm establishes that the challenged constitutional rule is incorrect. Finally, and assuming that it is able to convince us of the incorrectness of the challenged rule, the state must persuade us that, when the passage of time and the precedential use of the challenged rule is factored in, overturning the rule will not unduly cloud or complicate the law.
With respect to the first task described above, we acknowledge that Robertson does not discuss at length the wording, history or case law surrounding the particular clause that has captured the state's attention -- that is, the "abuse" clause of Article I, section 8. That is so, most likely, because the parties in that case did not emphasize it. As such, we properly may consider the state's request that we conduct a more complete application of the appropriate paradigm to that aspect of Article I, section 8, than the Robertson court was called upon to do. In doing so, however, we once again emphasize that our consideration of such arguments in this or any other similar case does not suggest that we automatically doubt the validity of the holding in the earlier decision. As we have explained respecting that question, the principle of stare decisis dictates that our assumption going into the inquiry is just the other way around. And, as our subsequent analysis will demonstrate in detail, our reexamination of Robertson in response to the state's argument leads us to conclude that the state has not established, in accordance with its burden discussed above, that Robertson incorrectly considered or decided the constitutional issues that the court there addressed under Article I, section 8.
As discussed, the Priest paradigm requires us to search for the intent of the persons who adopted Article I, section 8 in three separate sources: (1) the text of the constitutional provision; (2) the case law surrounding it; and (3) the historical circumstances leading to its adoption. We turn to that paradigmatic process.
III. ANALYSIS OF ARTICLE I, SECTION 8
A. Wording
As noted, Article I, section 8, of the Oregon Constitution provides:
"No law shall be passed restraining the free expression of opinion, or restricting the right to speak, write, or print freely on any subject whatever; but every person shall be responsible for the abuse of this right."
The first half of the provision is directed at the legislature and other lawmaking bodies ("No law shall be passed * * *."). The provision prohibits enactment of two categories of laws: (1) those that "restrain[] the free expression of opinion," and (2) those that "restrict[] the right to speak, write or print freely on any subject whatever." The latter category of laws appears to deal only with various modes of communication that use words (i.e., speech, printing, or writing), while the first category seemingly includes laws directed at any mode of "expression." (4) The broad category of "expression" is narrowed somewhat by the specification that the expression be an expression of "opinion." That phrase, "expression of opinion," thus appears to refer to expression that, in some way, appraises or judges an object, person, action, or idea. (5) But the concept is not in terms limited to opinion that is communicated by means of words, i.e., expression that is spoken, written, or printed. The phrase could, for example, include nonverbal "artistic" forms of expression like painting, photography, and dance, which often are designed to convey something about the communicator's world view.
The two categories of laws that are prohibited by the first part of Article I, section 8, may be distinguished in another way -- by the choice of the terms "restrain" and "restrict." Respecting those terms, it is sufficient here to say that we read the first phrase as referring to laws that restrain or punish expression of opinion (6) and the second phrase as referring to laws that limit speaking, writing, or printing on any subject. Needless to say, that is a very broad prohibition. It precludes any restraint on most forms of expression as well as laws directed at limiting or restricting any conceivable kind of communication.
The second half of Article I, section 8 ("but every person shall be responsible for the abuse of this right"), describes an exception or modification to the broad guarantee (i.e., "this right") set out in the first half. The import of that "abuse clause" depends on the intended meaning of two words -- "responsible" and "abuse."
One may be "responsible" for abuse in a number of ways. Although Article I, section 8, logically could be read as referring only to moral responsibility, we think it unlikely that either the framers of the Oregon Constitution or those who voted to adopt it would have viewed a moral admonition as an appropriate subject for a substantive provision of their constitution. Instead, we think it inescapable that the term must be read as referring to legal accountability for any "abuse" of the expansive right described in the first clause of Article I, section 8. However, the word alone does not make clear whether, for example, such legal accountability is limited to civil damages, or also may be extended to criminal punishment. (7)
When used as a noun, the term "abuse" meant, at or around the time that it was adopted in Article I, section 8:
"1. Ill use; improper treatment or employment; application to a wrong purpose; as an abuse of our natural powers; an abuse of civil rights; or of religious privileges; abuse of advantages, etc.
"* * * * *
"5. Perversion of meaning; improper use or application; as an abuse of words."
Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (emphasis in original). "Abuse," in the context of Article I, section 8, thus appears to mean improper use -- that is, use of the right provided by the first clause in a way or for a purpose that, under some unidentified standard, is improper or wrongful. Beyond that, however, the provision offers no further hint as to how abuse of the right granted in the first clause of Article I, section 8, may be distinguished from a proper use of that right.
B. Case Law
Following our paradigm, we turn to a review of cases that were decided under Article I, section 8, before the Robertson decision. We think that it is fair to summarize those cases by saying that they tended to rely, expressly or implicitly, on federal First Amendment jurisprudence. When Article I, section 8, explicitly was at issue, this court tended to view the abuse clause of Article I, section 8, as permitting laws aimed at punishing (as opposed to imposing prior restraints on) expression itself. (8) See, e.g., State v. Jackson, 224 Or 337, 349-52, 356 P2d 495 (1960) (sustaining indictment for selling, distributing, and possessing obscene book; observing that Article I, section 8, of the Oregon Constitution appears to adopt Blackstonian view that freedom of speech means only freedom from prior restraint); City of Portland v. Welch, 229 Or 308, 322, 367 P2d 403 (1961) (although city movie licensing ordinance violated Article I, section 8, because it amounted to prior restraint, that constitutional provision "does not prohibit sending convicted obscenity dealers to jail"); State v. Laundy, 103 Or 443, 204 P 958 (1922) (criminal syndicalism laws aimed at punishing speech that advocates revolution did not violate Article I, section 8).
Although no pre-Robertson case contains a systematic analysis of the meaning of Article I, section 8, standing alone, the Jackson court made some effort in that direction. The court there quoted Blackstone on the issue of liberty of the press and noted that Blackstone's analysis -- that liberty of the press meant only freedom from prior restraint -- had been criticized by at least one notable constitutional scholar as unworkable and inconsistent with eighteenth-century history. Jackson, 224 Or at 346-47. Having identified the issue, however, the Jackson court concluded, without further explanation or analysis, that Article I, section 8 "adopt[s] the formula of [Blackstone's] Commentaries." Id. at 348.
That brings us to Robertson -- the case that, as we have noted, has become the source of our present framework for analyzing issues that arise under Article I, section 8. We discuss the case in some detail. Before doing so, we note in passing that, in a way, it is curious that Robertson should have become the lightning rod for disputes under Article I, section 8. On its face, the case was (and is) a straightforward effort at comparing a statute with the Oregon Constitution and determining whether the two could co-exist. Nothing in the opinion announces, at last explicitly, that it intends to state a new and different standard for interpreting the scope of Article I, section 8.
Robertson involved challenges under the First Amendment and Article I, section 8, to the then-current version of the statute defining the crime of coercion. The court declined to consider the First Amendment argument, preferring to map out and utilize an analysis that focused particularly on Oregon's free expression provision, Article I, section 8.
Drawing on comments in an earlier case, State v. Spencer, 289 Or 225, 611 P2d 1147 (1980), the Robertson court opined that Article I, section 8, is a restriction on lawmakers, prohibiting them from enacting restrictions that are directed by their terms at expression:
"As stated above, Article I, section 8, prohibits lawmakers from enacting restrictions that focus on the content of speech or writing, either because that content itself is deemed socially undesirable or offensive, or because it is thought to have adverse consequences. This is the principle applied in State v. Spencer, supra. It means that laws must focus on proscribing the pursuit or accomplishment of forbidden results rather than on the suppression of speech or writing either as an end in itself or as a means to some other legislative end."
Robertson, 293 Or at 416-17. The court then went on to say, however, that there is an exception to that rule –- specifically, that laws that are directed at restraining expression are permissible when the "scope of the restraint is wholly confined within some historical exception that was well established when the first American guarantees of freedom of expression were adopted and that the guarantees then or in 1859 demonstrably were not intended to reach." Id. at 412. The court specifically identified, as examples, the crimes of "perjury, solicitation or verbal assistance in crime, some forms of theft, forgery and fraud and their contemporary variants." Id.
The Robertson court next held that, even when a statute is written to focus on some forbidden result, it is subject to closer scrutiny if it proscribes one or more modes of expression as a means to that end:
"When the proscribed means include speech or writing, however, even a law written to focus on a forbidden effect * * * must be scrutinized to determine whether it appears to reach privileged communication or whether it can be interpreted to avoid such 'overbreadth.'"
Id. at 417-18. The court noted that, on the other hand, when a law is directed only against causing a forbidden effect, a person accused of causing that effect by means of expression "would be left to assert * * * that the statute could not constitutionally be applied to his particular words or other expression, not that it was drawn and enacted contrary to [A]rticle I, section 8." Id. at 417. That is to say, the person would have to object to the statute on a narrow, "as applied" basis.
The Robertson court did not inquire directly into the intent of the people who drafted and adopted Article I, section 8, or mention any other methodology as a basis for its analysis. However, the central points in Robertson -- the propositions that Article I, section 8, is directed at lawmakers and laws, and that it precludes the adoption of laws that are directed at restraining expression -- derive directly from certain words of the provision.
As noted, the Robertson framework has become the consistent basis for examining any challenge under Article I, section 8. Among the many cases that have been decided according to that framework are a number that are particularly relevant here, because they involve attempts to ban or regulate expression that has sexual content. In State v. Henry, 302 Or 510, 732 P2d 9 (1987), for example, this court used the Robertson framework in holding that a statute prohibiting the possession of obscene material violated the free expression guarantee of Article I, section 8, because it was directed, by its terms, at a type of expression. Notably, the court rejected the state's contention that prohibitions on obscenity fall within a historical exception to the guarantee: While the state was able to show that various legal prohibitions on "lewd" conduct and publications existed during the eighteenth and nineteenth century, the Henry court concluded that there was no "well-established" exception equivalent to the acknowledged exceptions for libel, perjury, and forgery. Id. at 520-22.
In the later case of City of Portland v. Tidyman, 306 Or 174, 759 P2d 242 (1988), the City of Portland attempted to regulate, rather than prohibit outright, obscene expression by enacting certain zoning restrictions on "adult" bookstores and businesses. The city prefaced the zoning restrictions with "findings" to the effect that "adult" businesses caused certain harmful effects and argued to this court that those findings established that the restrictions were directed at harmful effects, rather than at expression. After noting that the ordinance did not make the adverse effects described in the findings an element of the regulatory standard, the Tidyman court concluded that the zoning ordinance was directed at expression and, thus, violated Article I, section 8. Tidyman, 306 Or at 185-86.
More recently, in State v. Stoneman, 323 Or 536, 920 P2d 535 (1996), this court applied the Robertson framework to a criminal statute directed at the producers and purchasers of visual reproductions of children engaged in sexually explicit conduct. This court examined the statute in its context and found that it was directed at a harmful effect -- unlawful sexual exploitation of children -- in that it made such exploitation a necessary element of any violation. The court concluded that the statute therefore passed muster under Article I, section 8. Id. at 550.
Our discussion of the foregoing cases illustrates how this court in recent years has applied the Robertson framework to Article I, section 8, challenges. In none of those cases, however, did this court attempt to evaluate systematically the text and other relevant material surrounding Article I, section 8, to determine what the people who drafted and adopted that provision intended by it.
A fair summary of all the cases that this court has decided under Article I, section 8, would be that, while earlier cases (such as Jackson) point one way, and later cases (such as Robertson and Henry) point another, the later cases do not expressly overrule the earlier ones. We turn to the historical circumstances surrounding the adoption of the provision.
C. Historical Circumstances
In its brief to this court, the state argues that, when viewed in the light both of earlier and contemporary thinking about the concept of free speech and expression, it is clear that Article I, section 8, as it was drafted in 1857, was intended only as a prohibition on prior restraints. According to the state, it also is clear that the "abuse clause" of Article I, section 8, was inserted in recognition of the power of the state to punish, after the fact, any speech that, because of its anti-social tendencies, the legislature deemed to be an "abuse."
The state's argument has some historical support. Certainly, there is evidence that, during the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, most American courts and legal treatises tended to treat the right of free speech as a very limited one, guaranteeing to the individual only a freedom from prior restraint. In fact, it now is widely accepted that, in adopting a prohibition on laws "abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press," as the First Amendment phrased it, many, if not most, of the framers of the First Amendment were thinking in terms of the English common-law notion of freedom of speech, which prohibited prior restraints on the press but did not preclude civil or criminal prosecution, after the fact, for obscene, blasphemous, libelous, or seditious speech. See generally Leonard W. Levy, The Emergence of a Free Press 220-81 (1985) (setting out that view). (9)
It is clear, moreover, that, throughout the nineteenth century, the most popular legal treatises equated the First Amendment and state constitutional guarantees of free speech primarily with freedom from prior restraint. See, e.g., William Rawle, A View of the Constitution of the United States of America (1829) (reprint ed. 1970) ("A previous superintendency of the press, an arbitrary power to direct or prohibit its publications are withheld, but the punishment of dangerous or offensive publications * * * is necessary for the peace and order of government and religion."); Thomas M. Cooley, A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations 421 (1868) ("[I]t is well understood and received as a commentary on this provision for the liberty of the press [i.e., the First Amendment], that it was intended to prevent all such previous restraints upon publications as had been practiced by other governments") (emphasis in original); Joseph Story, 2 Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States 667-68 (1858) reprinted in Philip B. Kurland and Ralph Lerner, eds., 5 The Founders' Constitution 181 (1987) ("It is plain, then, that the language of this amendment imports no more, than that every man shall have a right to speak, write and print his opinions on any subject whatever, without any prior restraint").
As the foregoing discussion suggests, most of the mainstream American discussions of the constitutional right to free speech drew heavily (sometimes without attribution) on Blackstone's explication of the common law pertaining to freedom of the press:
"[W]here blasphemous, immoral, treasonable, schismatical, seditious or scandalous libels are punished by the English law * * * the liberty of the press, properly understood, is by no means infringed or violated. The liberty of the press is indeed essential to the nature of a free state; but this consists in laying no previous restraints upon publications, and not in freedom from censure for criminal matter when published. Every freeman has an undoubted right to lay what sentiments he pleases before the public: * * * but if he publishes what is improper, mischievous, or illegal, he must take the consequences of his own temerity. * * * * *. Thus the will of individuals is still left free; the abuse only of that free-will is the object of legal punishment. * * * * *
"So true will it be found, that to censure the licentiousness, is to maintain the liberty of the press."
William Blackstone, 4 Commentaries on the Laws of England 151-52 (1783 ed.) (reprint ed. 1978). Following Blackstone, American legal treatises described the government's power to punish the "licentiousness" of the press, or the "abuse" of the right of free speech. See Cooley, A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations at 420 (the right guarantees "the liberty of the press, not its licentiousness"); Story, 2 Commentaries on the Constitution at 670 (prohibiting prior restraint but permitting punishment of "dangerous or offensive" expression is proper because "the will of individuals is still left free [and] the abuse only of that free will is the object of legal punishment").
But what constituted "abuse" under that formulation? On that point, the mainstream legal treatises again tended to treat Blackstone as the oracle: His pronouncements -- that liberty of speech does not extend to publications that are "improper, mischievous, or illegal" or that are "on a fair and impartial trial * * * adjudged of a pernicious tendency" -- often were repeated and endorsed. See, e.g., Story, 2 Commentaries on the Constitution at 670-71 (repeating the foregoing phrases from Blackstone). Thus, many respected early and mid-nineteenth century jurists and legal writers appear to have believed that "abuse" covered at least some speech that the governing authority deemed to have anti-social tendencies or to threaten the public peace. That Blackstonian formulation, purporting to be a restatement of the English common law, (10) extended to broad categories of speech including, apparently, libel, seditious libel, blasphemy, and obscenity. (11)
On the whole, the nineteenth century American judiciary appeared to have shared that limited view of the right to free speech. See, e.g., Respublica v. Dennie, 4 Yeates 518, 2 Am Dec 402, 405-06 (Pa 1805) ("Publish as you please in the first instance without control; but you are answerable both to the community and to the individual, if you proceed to unwarrantable lengths"); Commonwealth v. Blanding, 20 Mass (3 Pick) 304, 313-14 (Mass 1825) (stating that the free speech provision in the Massachusetts Constitution was intended to prevent previous restraints on publication and does not abrogate the common law, including the then-prevalent common law understanding that, in libel prosecution, truth may not be asserted as defense); Commonwealth v. Kneeland, 37 Mass (20 Pick) 206, 219 (Mass 1838) (the obvious intent behind the free speech provision in Massachusetts Constitution was to prevent the enactment of licence laws or other direct restraints upon publication).
At most, the judiciary would concede to a slightly more liberal version of the Blackstonian view -- that, in addition to prohibiting prior restraint, freedom of speech and of the press incorporated a "right to publish, with impunity, truth, with good motives, and for justifiable ends, whether it respects government, magistracy, or individuals." People v. Croswell, 3 Johns Cas 335, 392-93 (NY 1804) (reciting that definition in the context of a prosecution under the Alien and Sedition Act); Pugh v. Starbuck, 1 Ohio Dec. Reprint 143, 149 (Ohio Sup 1845) (quoting Croswell). See also James Kent, II Commentaries on American Law 17-25 (3d ed. 1836) (accepting view that individuals may be criminally punished for challenging individuals or the government in print, but stating that, contrary to Blackstone, the truth of the publication should be available as a defense). That variation on Blackstone's formulation did not challenge the legislature's power to punish undesirable speech, but did extend to defendants threatened with criminal punishment for libel an opportunity to demonstrate their own good motives and the truth of the matter in question.
Interestingly, the foregoing view of the right of free speech was contrary, in many respects, to the philosophy that had animated the American Revolution. Many of the leading lights of the American revolutionary period were greatly influenced by the "natural rights" philosophy that was advanced in the works of John Locke and that later was popularized, and fused with the republican political tradition, by John Trenchard and Thomas Gordon under the nom de plume "Cato." See generally Levy, The Emergence of a Free Press at 109-14 (describing Cato's Letters and noting that the letters were revered, quoted, and recommended by the likes of John Adams, Thomas Jefferson, Benjamin Franklin, Josiah Quincy, and John Dickinson). On the issue of freedom of speech, Cato wrote:
"Without Freedom of Thought, there can be no such Thing as Wisdom; and no such Thing as publick Liberty, without Freedom of Speech; Which is the Right of every Man, as far as by it does not hurt and controul the Right of another; and this is the only Check which it ought to suffer, the only Bounds which it ought to know."
"Of Freedom of Speech", No 15, Feb 4, 1720, in John Trenchard and Thomas Gordon, I Cato's Letters: Essays on Liberty, Civil and Religious 96 (reprint ed. 1971)
To the more libertarian adherents of the natural rights philosophy, freedom of speech was an "inalienable" natural right -- that is, it was not part of the package of natural rights that individuals ceded to the community in order to obtain the protections and benefits of civil society. Rather, it was a right that the individual always retained, as he or she would in a state of nature. Even for natural rights adherents, however, the right was not absolute. According to the natural rights theory, inalienable rights, such as freedom of conscience and speech, were bounded, as they were in the state of nature, by the equally fundamental rights of other individuals. If the state had any authority at all to act in these protected areas, it was to enforce the fundamental rights of other individuals, not to protect society as a whole from undesirable "tendencies" or to promote the majority's idea of the greater good. That is decidedly different from the Blackstonian notion of "abuse", (12) which extended to everything that Parliament had identified as contrary to the public good (a notion that included purely social values like order, morality, and religion).
Thus, and particularly in reaction to the ill-advised Alien and Sedition Act of 1798, some early American political thinkers would speak in terms of an "absolute" right of freedom of speech and press, bounded only by the necessity of avoiding injury to the equal rights of another individual. Madison, for example, argued that the First Amendment denied to Congress any power to regulate speech or the press, prospectively or retrospectively, but still expressed concern that individuals have a remedy for injury to their reputations and suggested that that was available under state laws. See generally James Madison, Report on the Virginia Resolutions (1800), reprinted in Kurland and Lerner, 5 The Founders' Constitution at 141-46 (criticizing the Alien and Sedition Act as contrary to the First Amendment and rejecting the idea that First Amendment merely adopted common law with respect to freedom of speech). St. George Tucker posited an absolute liberty of speech without restraint, "except as to the injury of any other individual in his person, property, or good name." St. George Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries: With Notes and References to the Constitution and Laws of the Federal Government of the United States (1803), reprinted in Kurland and Lerner, 5 The Founders' Constitution at 152-58. George Hay, a member of the Virginia House of Delegates, insisted that freedom of the press consisted of absolute freedom to publish what one pleases, "provided he does no injury to any other individual." Hortensius [George Hay], "An Essay on the Liberty of the Press" (1799), in George Hay, Two Essays on the Liberty of the Press, 21, 23 (reprint ed. 1970). (13) Other notable early speech "libertarians" included Tunis Wortman, who wrote A Treatise Concerning Political Enquiry and the Liberty of the Press (1800), and John Thomson, who wrote An Enquiry Concerning the Liberty and Licentiousness of the Press (1801).
Although we tend to associate the notion of natural, inalienable rights with the founding of our nation, it is important to note that that idea continued as an important legal and political philosophy until the latter part of the nineteenth century. (14) The theory held particular appeal for the Americans participating in the great westward movement, who often had moved west to avoid the constraints of settled society and tended to place an especially high value on individual liberty. Records of the constitutional conventions of pioneer states are replete with affirmations of the natural rights theory, (15) and many of those states adopted constitutional provisions or preambles expressly declaring the "inalienable natural rights" of man. See, e.g., Ill Const (1848), Art XIII, § 1 (declaring man's natural and inalienable rights); Ind Const (1851), Art I, § 1 (same); Iowa Const (1857), Art I, § 1 (same); Kan Const (1861), § 1 (same); Nev Const (1864), Art I, § 1 (same); Wis Const (1848), Art I, § 1 (same). Some western courts utilized natural-rights thinking in their opinions, rejecting the "general welfare" or "police powers" doctrine that was increasingly being used by state courts to support the idea that private rights always must give way to the social interest in public welfare, safety, and good morals, (16) or holding that such power is limited to or must be based on actual injuries to others. (17)
The struggle over the efficacy of natural rights played a significant role in the defining political issue of the nineteenth century, slavery. Natural rights ideas were taken up wholeheartedly by anti-slavery Republicans, who used them to challenge the legality of slavery. Daniel Farber and Suzanna Sherry, A History of the American Constitution 258-71 (1990). But abolitionists and anti-slavery Republicans also had a special interest in the free speech implications of the natural rights theory. The abolitionist message was highly unpopular in most of the United States, and the proponents of the message were acutely aware of the threat to free speech presented by majority rule. (18)
Abolitionists therefore argued that legislatures -- the instruments of the majority -- had no constitutional power to suppress or punish speech because of its supposed "bad tendencies" vis-à-vis the public peace. See, generally, Michael K. Curtis, Free Speech: "The People's Darling Privilege" 10-13, 194-215 (2000) (describing prevailing "bad tendency" rationale for suppressing unpopular speech and rejection of that rationale by abolitionists and Republicans). However, consistent with traditional natural rights theory, they acknowledged that the God-given right to free expression was limited by the equal rights of others. See Steven J. Heyman, Righting the Balance, An Inquiry into the Foundations and Limits of Freedom of Expression, 78 B U L Rev 1275, 1297 n 124 (1998) (quoting speeches and writings of abolitionists, including James G. Birney and the Rev. Elijah Lovejoy).
In general, then, we can see that Article I, section 8, was adopted at a time in American history when much of the legal community was content with a narrow, Blackstonian view of freedom of speech, but when a more libertarian approach, which was associated with the natural right theory that initially had animated the American Revolution -- still enjoyed significant popular adherence. (19) That background suggests the question: Which one (if either) of those theories did the framers of Article I, section 8, intend to adopt when they included the "abuse" clause in Article I, section 8? The first place to look for the answer to that question is the direct history of Article I, section 8. We turn to that history now.
We know that Article I, section 8, was part of the original Oregon Constitution and was derived from the free speech guarantee in Indiana's 1851 constitution. (20) Charles Henry Carey, ed., The Oregon Constitution and Proceedings and Debates of the Constitutional Convention of 1857 468 (1926). As this court acknowledged in Jackson, the wording is not peculiar to Oregon and Indiana, and was widely used in other state constitutions, beginning with the Pennsylvania Constitution of 1790. Jackson, 224 Or at 348-49.
There is no record of any specific discussion of Article I, section 8, at Oregon's Constitutional Convention in 1857. However, we do have a record of comments made during the Constitutional Convention about a proposed amendment to another provision of the draft constitution that shows that a range of points of view was present there. Specifically, Carey reports that, on September 9, 1857, delegate Perry B. Marple moved to amend proposed Article I, section 10, of the draft constitution to provide that, in "prosecutions" for libel, the truth may be given in mitigation of damages, rather than in "justification." Carey, The Oregon Constitution and Proceedings and Debates of the Constitutional Convention of 1857 at 309. The omnipresent Matthew Deady moved to make the provision even less protective (21) and suggested, by way of illustration, that the editor of the San Francisco Bulletin was guilty of a "malicious use of power" with regard to certain stories that had appeared in that newspaper. Id. at 309-10. Thomas Dryer, then editor of the Oregonian, a Whig newspaper, complained bitterly about the suggested amendments as attempts to muzzle the press and suggested that "the previous section [which was to become Article I, section 8] covered all the ground." Id. at 310. Delegate George Williams (22) apparently agreed with Dryer that Article I, section 8, "embraced all that was required" and moved to strike the provision pertaining to libel altogether. Id. A rather lengthy "debate" between Dryer and Deady ensued, with Deady decrying the "irresponsible public press" and Dryer stating that it would be strange if the press were to be debarred from denouncing corruption and villainy. Dryer also said, in apparent reference to Article I, section 8, that
"it was also strange that the whole judiciary should lock hands together on this subject. When the newspapers spoke of any prominent official -- and told the truth -- it was invariably characterized as 'abuse.'"
Id.
The dispute between Deady and Dryer suggests that there was no clear agreement among the delegates as to the meaning of the term "abuse" in the context of Article I, section 8. In fact, Dryer seemed to have feared a different kind of "abuse," one in which a conservative judiciary would abuse its authority to interpret the Oregon Constitution to undermine the very freedom that, in Dryer's view, Article I, section 8, sought to guarantee. Neither does it appear that there was any clear winner in the dispute: the delegates may have concluded that Article I, section 8, "covered all the ground," but they did not feel compelled to further clarify the abuse clause.
As to the question whether the original Oregon Constitution reflects a Blackstonian view of individual rights or, instead, has a natural rights focus, the evidence also is mixed. This court previously has noted that the original constitution, as a whole, reflects a basic distrust of legislative power. See Smothers, 332 Or at 113 (so stating). Such distrust would be more consistent with a natural rights-based world view. Certain comments made by delegates to the constitutional convention support that theory. One delegate argued for inclusion of a bill of rights in the constitution on the ground that it would limit the "fractious" spirit of the majority if it tried to "infringe on the rights of the individual citizen." See Carey, The Oregon Constitution and Proceedings and Debates of the Constitutional Convention of 1857 at 102 (comments of delegate Delazon Smith). Another delegate suggested that a bill of rights was necessary only to control a despotic ruler and was irrelevant when the people are sovereign. Id. at 102-103 (comments of delegate George Williams). The fact that the framers ultimately opted to include a bill of rights suggests acceptance of the view that at least some individual rights should not be subject to the whims of the majority.
On the other hand, unlike their counterparts in many western states, the framers of the Oregon Constitution did not include any express announcement of the "inalienable" natural rights of man in their constitution. They were content to announce that "all men, when they form a social compact, are equal in right" and that "all power is inherent in the people." Or Const, Art I, § 1. The absence of any declaration of "inalienable" natural rights was noted and decried by some Oregonians at the time, (23) but probably did not affect the ultimate decision to adopt the constitution. As one contemporary commentator put it, "This objection is not sufficient to deter a man really favorable to State government from voting for the Constitution." Claudia Burton and Andrew Grade, A Legislative History of the Oregon Constitution of 1857 -- Part I (Articles I and II), 37 Willamette L Rev 469, 491-92 (2001) (quoting letters to the editor printed in Oregon Argus on October 17, 1857).
D. The Framers' Intent
It is against the foregoing textual, historical, and jurisprudential background that we must assess the state's assertion that the Robertson framework is contrary to the intent of the people who drafted and adopted Article I, section 8. That assessment necessarily involves an attempt to ascertain, from the information that we have gathered, the framers' intent with respect to the scope and meaning of Article I, section 8.
Turning our focus to the first clause of Article I, section 8, one is struck by its sweeping terms, both with respect to the legislative power ("[n]o" law shall be passed restraining * * * or restricting) (emphasis added) and the kinds of expression protected ("* * * the free expression of opinion, or * * * the right to speak, write, or print freely on any subject whatever") (emphasis added). In fact, the words are so clear and sweeping that we think that we would not be keeping faith with the framers who wrote them if we were to qualify or water them down, unless the historical record demonstrated clearly that the framers meant something other than what they said. As our recitation of the historical circumstances shows, we have found no such demonstration. Thus, it appears to us to be beyond reasonable dispute that the protection extends to the kinds of expression that a majority of citizens in many communities would dislike -- profanity, blasphemy, pornography -- and even to physical acts, such as nude dancing or other explicit sexual conduct, that have an expressive component. Thus, we have little trouble in concluding that the people who framed and adopted Article I, section 8, as part of the original Oregon Constitution intended to prohibit broadly any laws directed at restraining verbal or nonverbal expression of ideas of any kind. (24)
We also conclude that those same people intended to provide an exception to that broad prohibition -- the legislature could provide legal and even criminal remedies for "abuse" of the right to free speech. That is evident from the fact that, however people might have disagreed as to what constituted "abuse" of the right of free expression, no one in the United States (with the possible exception of George Hay) was arguing, at that time, that the government never could impose criminal penalties, even as a remedy for an undeniable abuse of the right of free expression.
The foregoing leaves us to sort out the pivotal conundrum inherent in Article I, section 8: What is the scope of the term, "the abuse of this right"? (25) As we have seen, based on the philosophical currents swirling through the mid-nineteenth century United States, two opposing answers suggest themselves. On the one hand, the framers of the Oregon Constitution may have intended that the section receive a classically Blackstonian construction, i.e., they may have been satisfied that the only limitation that need be placed on legislative interference with free expression was a denial of the ability to impose prior restraints. If that were the case, then "abuse" of the right of free expression included anything that was deemed to be such by the majority. On the other hand, the framers of the Oregon Constitution may have intended that the section receive a classically natural rights construction, allowing no punishment of expression qua expression, even after the fact. In that case, an individual's responsibility for "abuse" of the fundamental right of free expression would be limited to expression that caused some injury to the equally fundamental rights of other individuals.
The difficulty, of course, is that there is no sound basis for placing "the framers," as a whole, into one or the other of those categories. Both views were represented at the Constitutional Convention (the exchange between Dreyer and Deady, described above, demonstrates as much) and, presumably, among the population that voted in 1857 to adopt the Oregon Constitution. There is scant evidence of any overt collision between the two philosophies (only the exchange between Dreyer and Deady, described above, might qualify). Certainly, there is no clear evidence that one or the other theory prevailed.
In short, no unassailably correct answer, based entirely on the provision's wording, case law, history, or any other objective evidence, is possible. The question then presents itself: In the face of the foregoing impasse about the framers' intent, can the state meet its burden of showing that the Robertson framework is contrary to the framers' intent with respect to Article I, section 8? Clearly, it can do so only if it demonstrates that Robertson is incompatible with both of the possible meanings of that provision that we have identified.
Doubtless, the state could demonstrate that Robertson is incompatible with the Blackstonian approach: The central tenet of that approach -- that any speech that the government deems to be improper or socially undesirable may be punished as "abuse" -- could not be farther from the Robertson rule. On the other hand, the Robertson approach appears to be largely, if not entirely, compatible with the pure "natural rights" approach that we have described. As discussed, that natural rights theory holds that only speech that directly interferes with or harms the fundamental rights of other individuals is punishable (either civilly or criminally) as "abuse." That notion is fully consonant with the idea expressed in Robertson that, although speech qua speech cannot be punished, acts causing "forbidden results" (which, presumably, would include acts causing harm to other individuals) can be punished, even if that result is reached by means of speech. (26)
We recognize, of course, that some aspects of the Robertson framework have no obvious connection to the "natural right" theory of free speech as we have described it. In particular, Robertson states that there are "historical exceptions" to the prohibition on laws restraining free expression and describes those exceptions as restrictions on speech that were "well established when the first American guarantees of freedom of expression were adopted and that the guarantees then or in 1859 demonstrably were not intended to reach." Robertson, 293 Or at 412. However, assuming that the drafters of Article I, section 8, intended to convey something akin to the "natural right" theory we have described, Robertson's "historical exception" idea does not clash with that intent. Instead, it merely recognizes that there are certain well-recognized traditional crimes that fall under the literal terms of the constitutional prohibition, but that the drafters "demonstrably" did not intend to abolish. The Robertson court may have realized that it was necessary to acknowledge such historical exceptions in order to carry out the drafters' intent. (27) In the end, then, Robertson's description of "historical exceptions" is not inconsistent with the framers' intent.
We have stated that, in light of this court's longstanding reliance on the Robertson framework to resolve issues that arise under Article I, section 8, the burden of demonstrating that that framework is inconsistent with the intent of the people who drafted and adopted Article I, section 8, lies with the party challenging that framework –- in this case, the state. It should be clear from the foregoing discussion that the state has failed to meet its burden: To the contrary, after applying the methodology set out in Priest to Article I, section 8, we are satisfied that the Robertson framework is justified. That framework is generally compatible with the "natural rights" approach that we have described as a possible source of Article I, section 8. Moreover, it is more consistent with that approach than the malleable and indistinct "balancing" test proposed by the state. We therefore will continue to analyze challenges brought under Article I, section 8, using the Robertson framework (including Robertson's notion of a historical exception).
Before we turn to the task of applying the Robertson framework to the case at hand, we believe that it is appropriate to address the "historical exception" aspect of the Robertson analysis with more particularity. It has become clear to this court, from the opinion below, the state's arguments in this and other recent cases, and certain commentary in the academic and professional literature, (28) that some students of this court's jurisprudence are intent on reading the historical exception idea of Robertson more broadly than the Robertson court intended. Those critics of Robertson focus exclusively on the words of the oft-quoted test from Robertson (29) and, from that standpoint, assume that a "historical exception" is made out by showing that laws prohibiting the expression at issue were more or less widespread at or before the adoption of the federal Bill of Rights and continued to exist in this state after 1859, when the Oregon Constitution was adopted. They do so in spite of the admonition against such thinking in Henry. In that case, this court emphasized that
"the constitutional guarantee of free speech and press will not be overcome by the mere showing of some legal restraints on one or another form of speech or writing. The party opposing a claim of constitutional privilege must demonstrate that the guarantees of freedom of expression were not intended to replace the earlier restrictions."
Henry, 302 Or at 521 (emphasis added.) We note also that Henry warned that
"'contemporaneous legislative actions should not necessarily be given much weight when construing constitutional principles. Constitutional draftsmen are concerned with broad principles of longstanding significance.'"
Id. at 521-22 (quoting State ex rel Oregonian Pub. Co. v. Deiz, 289 Or 277, 284, 613 P2d 23 (1980)).
To be sure, this court has not elaborated on those passages from Henry to explain what a party must show in order to demonstrate that the drafters of Article I, section 8, did not intend to abolish a well-established pre-existing restriction on expression. (30) However, Robertson contains some comments that, in our view, are relevant to the problem.
Se